Найти тему

и

Abstract
Following the levels of intentionality and semiosis distinguished by the Semiotic
Hierarchy (a layered model of semiosis/intentionality), and the distinction between
original agency (without the use of artefacts) and enhanced agency (the prosthetic
incorporation of artefacts), we propose a model of an agency hierarchy, consisting
of six layers. Consistent with the phenomenological orientation of cognitive semi-
otics, a central claim is that agency and subjectivity are complementary aspects of
intentionality. Hence, there is no agency without at least the minimal sense/feeling
of agency. This perspective rules out all artefacts as genuine agents, as well as sim-
ple organisms, since it is highly unlikely that e.g. bacteria have any first-person per-
spective. Using this model, we review and assess recent proposals on the nature of
agency from cognitive science, and neuroscience, and draw conclusions on how to
incorporate aspects of them within a synthetic cognitive-semiotic framework.
Keywords Agency hierarchy · Agentive semiotics · Cognitive semiotics · Enhanced
agency · Phenomenology · Semiotic hierarchy
Introduction: What Is Agency?
As with many philosophical notions, the concept of agency is contentious and
ambiguous. Although studies of issues related to agency can be traced back to Aris-
totle (Schauber, 2003), the use of the term in English does not occur before the
fifteenth century (Tønnessen, 2015; Schlosser, 2019). Etymologically, the word
derives from the Indo-European root ag- “to drive, draw out or forth, move” (Wat-
kins, 2000), used in Greek as ἄγω [agw] “lead towards a point, lead on”. In Latin it
acquired the sense “to drive at something, to pursue a course of action”, as in the
* Juan Mendoza-Collazos
juan.mendoza@semiotik.lu.se
1 Cognitive Semiotics, Center for Language and Literature, Lund University, Lund, Sweden
2 Universidad Nacional de Colombia, Bogotá, Colombia
Biosemiotics (2022) 15:141–170
Received: 1 December 2021 / Accepted: 2 February 2022 / Published online: 12 March 2022Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 2

1 3words agēns, agent-, agentia, and the adjective ăgens “efficient, effective, powerful”
(Lewis & Short, 1879). By 1650, the term is used in the sense of “active operation, a
mode of exerting power or producing effect” (Harper, 2021). The currently popular
sense “establishment where business is done for another” commenced two centuries
later.
In a very broad sense, agency can be attributed to any entity entering into a
causal relationship with another, leading to notions like “material agency” (Mala-
fouris, 2013), which risks emptying the concept of meaning, given that every sin-
gle entity in the universe can be endowed with some causal effectiveness. On the
other extreme, agency is commonly understood in philosophy as “the capacity to
act intentionally, and the exercise of agency consists in the performance of inten-
tional actions” (Schlosser, 2019). It should be noted that here the term ‘intentional’
is used, again as commonly, in the sense of deliberate, implying a degree of reflec-
tive consciousness. We are left with a conundrum: is agency just about everywhere
in nature, or is it a unique property of human actions, and at that for only for some of
them, those that are produced with deliberate, explicit goals?
To help answer this question, we may turn to semiotics, since agency and mean-
ing-making according to many scholars are closely related notions (Barandiaran
et al., 2009). But the answers we are likely to receive would depend on the kind of
semiotic theory we consult, given well-known differences between the “anthropose-
miotics” of who see meaning as a product of human minds and cultures (e.g. Eco,
1981; Morris, 1971), and those who extend meaning-making, and even sign-use, to
most, if not all, non-human animals, as typical for biosemiotics (e.g. Von Uexküll,
1982; Sebeok, 1999).1
One possible way to help resolve this dilemma is to turn to a comprehensive
semiotic theory that avoids the “bios vs. anthropo” dichotomy, at the same time
as it places agency at central stage. In his Agentive Semiotics, Niño (2015) defines
agency with respect to a number of conditions. From the standpoint of the agent,
the three basic conditions are those of animation (self-movement), situatedness and
attention.2 According to this theory, the agent necessarily has a (conscious or uncon-
scious) goal, an agenda. This agenda, on its side, depends both on the agent’s prior
actions and on the restrictions from the environment. Niño’s approach aims to inte-
grate different levels of agency, from simpler forms with a basic survival agenda,
to the cognitive agency of animals capable of self-awareness, to even higher forms
typical of human beings.
While inspired by such ideas, we take several steps back, and address agency
from the standpoint of cognitive semiotics, which is not a particular theory, but a
new science (in the broad sense of the term) dedicated to the study of meaning (also
1 See Sonesson and Zlatev (2009, eds.) for a Special Issue of the journal Cognitive Semiotics on the
topic of “Anthroposemiotics vs. Biosemiotics”, showing, among other things, that there are different
varieties of either, as well as positions such the present one, which is in several respects intermediary.
2 Niño (2015) explains in detail each of these conditions, key theoretical concepts such as emotion,
enaction, context, norms, actions and events, and how meaning making and agency are intrinsically
related. For a summary, see Mendoza-Collazos (2016).
142 J. Mendoza-Collazos, J. ZlatevContent courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 3

1 3in the broadest sense), combining methods and concepts from semiotics, cognitive
science and linguistics, with the help of phenomenology (Konderak, 2018; Sones-
son, 2012, 2015; Zlatev, 2015, 2018). In Section 2, we explain some of the basic
methodological principles of cognitive semiotics, and how they compel us to com-
bine experiential accounts of the studied phenomenon, with more detached, “objec-
tive” ones. Given that our phenomenon of study is that of agency, we propose a
general definition that is meant to be applicable to “biology, phenomenology, and
the sciences of mind”, to quote the subtitle of Thompson (2007). Consistent with
the level-based approach of Niño (2015), but more closely related to a cognitive-
semiotic theory known as the Semiotic Hierarchy (Zlatev, 2009, 2018; Zlatev &
Konderak, in press), and recent proposals to distinguish between basic (bodily) and
enhanced (with artefacts and signs) agency (Mendoza-Collazos & Sonesson, 2021),
we present an agency hierarchy, where higher levels presuppose, but go beyond,
lower ones.
Armed with these notions, we turn to a review of several recent theoretical pro-
posals on the nature of agency in cognitive science (Section 3) and neuroscience
(Section 4). Given that cognitive semiotics is predicated on the “conceptual-empir-
ical loop” (see Section 2), our aim is to be both critical and constructive in this
review, collecting insights for possible future trans-disciplinary studies of agency
along the way. We spell out some of these along with our conclusions in Section 5.
Cognitive Semiotics and Agency
Cognitive semiotics arose during the past two decades through collaborations of
cognitive scientists, semioticians and linguists who were dissatisfied by the limits
of their respective fields. Cognitive science, especially in more recent approaches
endorsing embodied, embedded, enactive, extended (or “4E cognition”) views on
the mind (Newen et al., 2018) is certainly broad, but often lacks deeper analyses
of meaning making and sign processes, of the kind that are typical for semiotics.
The latter, on its side, has often proposed rather general, and empirically under-
supported theories, even when attempting syntheses across the traditional sciences
(Eco, 1999). Linguistics continues to be locked in debates concerning what exactly
is “language”, from narrow computational views (Hauser et al., 2002), to broad
“multimodal” views (Vigliocco et al., 2014). While the latter have been much more
compatible with semiotics and cognitive science than the former, there has been a
regrettable tendency to extend the concept of “language” to any kind of semiotic
system, blurring fundamental differences in the material and semiotic properties that
distinguish them (Zlatev, 2019).
While there are different approaches and theories within cognitive semiotics, as
within any discipline, most of these have to a greater or lesser degree been influ-
enced by phenomenology, the systematic study of lived experience (Sokolowski,
2000). The non-dualist but also anti-reductionist and open-minded take of phenom-
enology on human experience has already resulted in multiple interdisciplinary
approaches within cognitive science, such as neurophenomenology, which “seeks
articulations by mutual constraints between the field of phenomena revealed by
143A Cognitive-Semiotic Approach to Agency: Assessing Ideas…Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 4

1 3experience and the correlative field of phenomena established by the cognitive sci-
ences” (Varela, 1996, p.347). A related notion is that of front-loaded phenomenol-
ogy, which “allow[s] the insights developed in phenomenological analyses […] to
inform the way experiments are set up” (Gallagher, 2003, p.91). However, cognitive
semiotics aims at more than putting phenomenology at the service of cognitive sci-
ence and neuroscience, as that would imply that the data from empirical studies are
given epistemological priority. This is manifestly not the case when human experi-
ence is concerned, since consciousness is not an empirical object on par with others
given its transcendental status, and cannot be “naturalized”, without extending our
understanding of nature itself (Merleau-Ponty, 1968; Zahavi, 2010).
Hence, cognitive semiotics professes two methodological principles. The first is
the conceptual-empirical loop (Stampoulidis, 2019; Zlatev, 2015) which postulates
that any investigation should begin not with assumed theories and the “predictions”
emanating from them (as in the standard “deductive-nomological model”), but with
careful reflections on the phenomenon under study, and the concepts used to analyse
it. Albeit in brief, this is how we began with the phenomenon of agency in Sec-
tion 1. Given such a preliminary conceptual investigation, we proceed to the empiri-
cal side, and review and conduct observations and experiments that are based on the
conceptual distinctions made, and emerging theories. The ambition is then to return
to the conceptual side better informed than at the onset, preparing the stage for a
new turn of the conceptual-empirical loop. The second principle is that of pheno-
methodological triangulation (Pielli & Zlatev, 2020), which states that every study
should explicitly combine methods from all three perspectives: first-person (intu-
ition-based), second-person (social interaction-based) and third person (detached
observation, e.g. experimentation), in this particular order of precedence. 3 Fig. 1
represents a combination of these two principles, showing at the same time the close
relation to similar ideas with famous pedigree, such as the “hermeneutic circle”.
One particular cognitive-semiotic theory that has emerged through the applica-
tion of these principles is the Semiotic Hierarchy (Zlatev, 2018). This is predicated
on the proposal that one of the main concepts of phenomenology, intentionality—
“the pointing-beyond itself proper of consciousness” (Thompson, 2007, p. 22) or
“the directional shape of experience” (Ihde, 2012, p. 24)—is layered, forming a
hierarchy of meaningfulness. The relation between the layers in the hierarchy is the
Husserlian notion of Fundierung, especially as elaborated by Merleau-Ponty (1962),
with “lower levels prefiguring the higher ones and higher ones consolidating and
sublimating the lowers ones, but without breaking away from them” (Zlatev, 2018,
p. 6).
3 As an anonymous reviewer points out, some considerations of such methodological triangulation have
also been taken from an explicitly biosemiotics perspective by Vehkavaara (2002). However, this pro-
posal gives least primacy for the first-person perspective (called “internal experience” and “introspec-
tion”), and even the second-person view seems to be subordinate to the third-person perspective, e.g.
“In the “phenomenology of the other one”, both the object-agent and the objects of the phenomenon that
the object-agent experiences must be possible objects of our external experience.” (ibid, p. 300). This is
converse to the primacy of the three perspectives in the pheno-methodological triangulation of cognitive
semiotics.
144 J. Mendoza-Collazos, J. ZlatevContent courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 5

1 3To each layer there is a dialectics of free activity (and thus agency) and norma-
tivity, with the latter emerging from sedimentations of such activity, thus forming a
dialectical spiral of spontaneity and sedimentation (Merleau-Ponty, 1962). The low-
est level in the hierarchy is that of drive and operative intentionality, and the subject
is here the animate and sensing body itself, as argued eloquently by Merleau-Ponty
(ibid, p. 296):
There is, therefore, another subject beneath me, for whom a world exists before
I am here, and who marks out my place in it. This captive or natural spirit is
my body, not that momentary body which is the instrument of my personal
choices and which fastens upon this or that world, but the system of anony-
mous ‘functions’ which draw every particular focus into a general project.
Above this layer is that of (focal) perceptual intentionality, which implies explicit
(thematic) consciousness and goal-directed attention. These are then precondi-
tions for intersubjectivity, the sharing of experiences between two or more subjects
(Zlatev, 2008), and thus for shared intentionality, with joint objects of attention and
goals. These first three layers of intentionality are more or less accessible to differ-
ent non-human animals (Preston & De Waal, 2002), but the highest two are uniquely
human. According to the theory, sign use is defined as the consciously accessible,
denotational relation between expression [E] and intentional object [O], and the
signitive intentionality corresponding to it is first made possible by bodily mimesis
(Zlatev, 2008; Zlatev et al., 2020). On the highest level of the hierarchy is symbolic
intentionality, made possible by using a highly articulated semiotic system such as
spoken language (Sokolowski, 2008), but of course also by signed languages, writ-
ten languages, and other modern (polysemiotic) media.
As implied by this brief summary, and as argued in the detail by Zlatev (2018),
the notion of intentionality is very intimately related to that of meaning-making
(semiosis), which should thus also be understood as layered. As Zlatev and Kon-
derak (in press) propose, while intentionality is “outward directed”, from conscious-
ness to the world, meaning-making is a kind of “ricochet” or inverse relation (see
Fig. 2), focusing on the experience of this intentionality, from the basic experience
Fig. 1 Combining the cognitive-semiotic principles of the conceptual-empirical loop and pheno-method-
ological triangulation
145A Cognitive-Semiotic Approach to Agency: Assessing Ideas…Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 6

1 3of spontaneous actions, to the interpretations of linguistic texts. Of course, this does
not in any way imply that semiosis is “passive”, only that while intentionality always
has its apex toward the world, semiosis is what this or that aspect of the world mat-
ters for the experiencing subject.
How could we understand agency in the context of this approach? Our proposal,
remaining to be validated through pheno-methodological triangulation (see above)
is that agency is nothing else but the active, self-generated aspect of intentional-
ity, which is also why the two concepts (and terms) intentionality and agency are
so often conflated. Conversely, subjectivity as the irreducible “qualitative feel” of
experience (and not the everyday use of the term to mean “bias”), can be seen as
the more subject-oriented aspect of intentionality, rather similarly to how Zlatev
and Konderak (in press) proposed understanding semiosis. A similar proposal has
recently also been made by a prominent current philosopher of life and mind:
Ordinary ways of thinking furnish us with a number of concepts that help us
get a handle on what minds do. One is the concept of subjectivity. This concept
arrives in a complementary pair with another: agency. Subjectivity is a matter
of seeming, of for-me-ness. It points to experience as something that happens
to a person. Agency is a matter of doing, trying, initiating. Agency is by-me-
ness; it is being a source of action and its effects. (Godfrey-Smith, 2020, p. 59)
We find this proposal of a reciprocal relation of subjectivity and agency as mutu-
ally complementing aspects of intentionality to be intuitive and consistent with a
phenomenological analysis of these notions, and at the same time productive for
empirical research. For example, Godfrey-Smith (2020) plausibly proposes that sub-
jectivity/agency emerged first in metazoa (animals), with multicellular bodies coor-
dinated by nervous systems, thus proposing a kind of third-person evidence. It is
thus consistent with our cognitive-semiotic approach in requiring first-person and
third-person evidence for the analysis. The second-person aspect here would consist
in whether we make the proposal intuitive for the reader as well. For example, the
definition of agency as the active aspect of intentionality, combined with a broad
Fig. 2 The reciprocal relation between intentionality and semiosis (meaning-making), adapted from
Zlatev and Konderak (in press)
146 J. Mendoza-Collazos, J. ZlatevContent courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 7

1 3reading of the latter in accordance with the Semiotic Hierarchy, implies that some
“instinctive” reactions, like moving your hand away quickly in response to burning
heat, should be understood as minimally agentive: while provoked by an external
“stimulus”, the movement away from the flame is experienced as my action, and not
as something purely mechanical.
The act of falling after being pushed is not agentive precisely because we experi-
ence, at least momentarily, the lack of the active, self-generated aspect of our being-
in-the-world (Gallagher & Zahavi, 2012), while all the movements being produced
to help ameliorate the fall do exhibit both agency and the sense of it (De Haan &
de Bruin, 2010). Such examples are often offered in the literature since they appeal
to the basic intuitions of most people. But there is more to both intentionality and
agency than bodily actions.
Recently, Mendoza-Collazos and Sonesson (2021) have explicated the notion
of enhanced agency: the prosthetic incorporation of artefacts to extend the origi-
nal agentive capacities of “the naked body”: the biological body, from a third-per-
son person perspective, or the lived body (Leib) from a first person perspective.
Enhanced agency emerges from the human ability to design objects that serve par-
ticular purposes, thus expanding agents’ ability to act and fulfil both individual and
shared goals. Some non-human animals have the ability to elaborate simple objects
from natural materials, using processes such as folding, joining, assembling, accu-
mulating, gluing and shaping (Hunt et al., 2006; McGrew, 2013), but the planned
improvement of artefacts establishes a fundamental difference between our and
other species (Mendoza-Collazos et al., 2021). Further, we need to highlight the dif-
ference between making an object and designing an artefact. The ability to design
implies innovation and continuous improvement. Enhanced agency is, then, a par-
ticular type of agency that is (among other features such as reflective consciousness,
signitive intentionality and language, see above) uniquely human, leading some to
characterize our species as “the animal that designs” (Colomina & Wigley, 2016).
Merging ideas from the Semiotic Hierarchy and the original vs. enhanced agency
distinction, we may propose a layered model of agency such as that shown in
Table 1: an agency hierarchy, where lower levels are necessary preconditions for
Table 1 An agency hierarchy: with lower levels standing in a Fundierung relation to higher ones, with
hypothetical evolutionary primacy, see text for explanations of the examples
Agency type Level/type of agency Examples of acts Examples of agents
Enhanced agency (6) Mediated by language
and other symbolic
media
An act of story-telling A community
(5) Sign-mediated Performing a pantomime A performance troupe
(4) Artefact-mediated Making a stone axe A manufacturer
Original agency (3) Joint Dancing in group A group of dancers
(2) Reflective Jumping up to pass over a barrier A high-jumper
(1) Operative Skilled movements without con-
scious attention, e.g. running
A runner
147A Cognitive-Semiotic Approach to Agency: Assessing Ideas…Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 8

1 3the emergence of higher levels of agency, both conceptually and in evolution, as we
indicate below. Given that agency and subjectivity are inextricable from the cor-
responding levels of intentionality, we require there to be a distinct experience, or
a sense of agency that corresponds to every layer of the hierarchy. This use of the
term “sense of agency” is consistent with – but both broader and more differentiated
than – the way it is used both in (phenomenological) cognitive science (Gallagher
& Zahavi, 2012), as well as in neuroscience, as we discuss in the following two
sections.
Let us briefly discuss examples of the different layers. With respect to the first
three layers of original agency, displayed bottom-up in Table 1, we can recognize
them not only in our own experience, but to some degree also in the behaviour of
other animals, using second-person methods (based on social interaction) and third-
person methods, like ethology and comparative psychology. The examples we pro-
vide below, however, are above all from human experience, given that we appeal to
the intuitions of our readers, and hence enact a form of second-person method (see
above).
Starting from operative agency, the act of running is always purposeful, per-
formed for numerous possible reasons (e.g. hunting, escaping, exercising). Yet,
the complex coordination of bodily movements required to carry this out does not
require conscious attention, allowing the runner to focus on something else, like
dodging obstacles. An explicit decision or “prior intention” to run does not need to
have taken place either. As Gallagher and Zahavi (2012, p. 178) point out concern-
ing a similar example:
I might act before I have a chance to decide to act. If, upon approaching the
bus stop, I see the bus pulling away, I might start running to catch it. If you
stop me and ask, ‘Are you trying to catch the bus?’ my answer would be yes,
that was my intention. But it is not clear that I had made any deliberation or
conscious decision to run after the bus. I might say, ‘I decided with my feet’,
meaning, my decision was in my action, not something separate from it. John
Searle (1983) calls this ‘intention-in-action’.
Reflective agency, on the other hand, does require a prior intention, and even the
ability to imagine the act in question in advance, for example an athlete practicing
high jumping. The agent here has to focus their full attention on the target, and (in
many cases) to “visualize” the movements they are to perform in order to succeed.
In the influential theory of human evolution proposed by (Donald, 1991, 2001,
2013), such imagination is one of the central functions of bodily mimesis as a form
of consciousness (Zlatev, 2019), before it becomes recruited for sign-based commu-
nication, as in pantomime (Zlatev et al., 2020).
Joint agency can be interpreted more narrowly as the product of explicit shared
intentions, as when the goal is to carry a heavy object together, or more broadly as
the spontaneous intersubjective coordination of movements in a group dance. Both
are in their more developed forms human-specific (Tomasello et al., 2005), and may
have played a key role in human evolution. But given the complexity of social lives
of some other animals like chimpanzees (De Waal, 2007) at least some more simple
forms of joint agency in non-human animals cannot be excluded.
148 J. Mendoza-Collazos, J. ZlatevContent courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 9

1 3On the other hand, we maintain that the three different layers of enhanced agency
– enhanced step-wise through artefacts, non-verbal signs and language (see Table 1)
– are properly conceived of as uniquely human. The simplest of these, artefact-medi-
ated agency, is epitomized in the acts of ancient tool-makers when they used natural
objects—like stones—as hammers and anvils to produce novel artefacts. While tool-
production is the oldest attested evidence of human manufacturing, it is possible that
other forms were made with perishable materials. In any case, such manufacturing
requires a complex step of procedures that implies complex conscious planning, far
exceeding not only intentions-in-action (see the citation above), but also prior inten-
tions. Donald (2013) claims again that bodily mimesis as conscious imagination
made this possible, and Vaesen (2012) reviews evidence that this capacity remains
unique for human beings, despite occasional claims to the contrary.
Even stronger is the evidence for the human specificity, on the population level,
of sign-mediated agency. This is the case because signs, on our understanding of
the concept, grounded in Husserlian phenomenology (Sonesson, 2007, 2015; Zlatev,
2018; Zlatev et al., 2020), imply conscious awareness of the representational sta-
tus of certain communicative material expressions (like words, gestures or pictures)
or even non-communicative phenomena (like natural symptoms). A key point is
that the initial human signs, in both evolution and development (Piaget & Inhelder,
2008) were not yet linguistic, but rather based on similarity (iconicity) or contiguity
(indexicality) with their referents. Even non-verbal signs have the capacity to allow
the agent greater freedom of reflection and action, by serving as a link between per-
ception and action (Vygotsky, 1978). This has also been observed in semiotically
enculturated non-human animals like the bonobo Kanzi and the chimpanzee Pan-
banisha, both with the privilege of extensive, and empathetic, training in sign use
(Persson, 2008; Savage-Rumbaugh & Lewin, 1994). A clear example of non-ver-
bal sign use that is apparently a human universal is pantomime (Żywiczyński et al.,
2018).
What language adds to this, and here even enculturated primates falter, is a com-
plex semiotic system of open-class (“categorematic”) signs, denoting objects, events
and properties, and closed-class (“syncategorematic”) signs, qualifying the former
and helping relate them, which is essential for complex communication and proposi-
tional thought (Sokolowski, 2008). Collective narratives such as myths are a natural
outgrowth (Collins, 2013; Donald, 1991), and help bond human communities into
powerful collective agents (Tomasello et al., 2012). Writing, and eventually media
combining language with other sign systems in polysemiotic communication have
enhanced human agency even more since then. One example would be the case of
modern corporate identity and branding in which a firm coordinates a full array of
communicative media under a unique, pre-established strategy, from the style of
written texts to an identifiable style of industrial design (Efer, 2017). We should
have this in mind when we consider discussions of the interrelations between agency
and design (e.g. Mendoza-Collazos et al., 2021).
To summarize, we have outlined in this section a particular cognitive-semiotic
model of agency, formulated a hierarchy that parallels the Semiotic Hierarchy,
understood as nested layers of intentionality and semiosis (Zlatev, 2018). A key
assumption, with grounds in both phenomenology and biological philosophy, is
149A Cognitive-Semiotic Approach to Agency: Assessing Ideas…Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 10

1 3that agency is the “other side of the coin” of subjectivity, understood as qualitative
phenomenal experience. Thus, there can be no agency without at least a minimal
“dosage” of the latter. On other words: no agency without (at least some) sense of
agency. This is the background against which we review and assess approaches to
agency in cognitive science and neuroscience in the following two sections.
Assessing Approaches to Agency in Cognitive Science
We review here three approaches to agency that all reflect recent trends in cognitive
science, where the mind is seen as enactive in organism-environment interactions,
according to which even simple organisms such as bacteria exhibit a basic kind of
agency (Barandiaran et al., 2009), or as extended beyond the body into artefacts,
as in Material Engagement Theory (Malafouris, 2013). As we show below, there
are complementary difficulties and advantages to these approaches, from the per-
spective of the cognitive-semiotic model of agency presented in Section 2. The third
approach, integrating phenomenology and cognitive science (Gallagher & Zahavi,
2012) distinguishes several layers of agency, and is both most compatible with the
agency hierarchy, and productive for neuroscience studies of agency, as we show in
Section 4.
An Enactive Approach to Agency
Varela et al. (1991) were in several respects prophetic some 30 years ago, by predict-
ing that the paradigm of cognitivism, based on the concepts of “symbolic” computa-
tions and representations (Fodor, 1983), and even connectionism, with its “sub-sym-
bolic” ditto (Feldman & Narayanan, 2004), are to be superseded in cognitive science
by a paradigm where cognition is redefined in more organic, interactionist and
(eventually) experiential terms. The rallying cry for this approach became enaction,
and the first definition of the latter was: “A history of structural coupling that brings
forth a world […] through a network consisting of multiple levels of interconnected,
sensorimotor subnetworks” (Varela et al., 1991, p.206). The origin of this concep-
tion lay in the notion of autopoiesis, the self-creation of living systems, forming a
closed system, and thus a form of identity, while at the same time remaining ther-
modynamically open and in constant interactions with the environment (Maturana &
Varela, 1987). A relevant addition was the notion of sense-making (De Jaegher & Di
Paolo, 2007) whereby organisms (and perhaps some other systems) actively seek to
improve their conditions of self-production, under precarious conditions. Combined
with autopoiesis, this “changes the physiochemical world into an environment of
significance and valence, creating an Umwelt” (Thompson, 2007, p.147), using the
term for the meaningful world introduced by von Uexküll (1982). It is on the basis
of this conceptual background that Barandiaran et al. (2009) explore the notion of
agency in an influential paper. As they point out:
The concept of agency plays a central role in contemporary cognitive sci-
ence as a conceptual currency across different sub-disciplines […] amena-
150 J. Mendoza-Collazos, J. ZlatevContent courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 11

1 3ble to dynamical systems’ modeling cutting across brain, body and world
and integrating different levels of mechanistic organization into the same
explanatory framework. (ibid. p. 1)
But at the same time, they note problems with lack of clear definitions on what
exactly constitutes agency and many metaphorical terms, not always recognized
as such. Hence, they propose three necessary and jointly sufficient conditions,
and consistent with these “a definition of minimal agency” (ibid. p. 11). In gen-
eral, we find this approach very convincing, and useful for our purposes, even as
the authors acknowledge lacunas in their work.
The first and most fundamental condition is that of individuality (identity, self-
hood), implying a distinction between the agentive system and the environment
that the system interacts with from its own point of view, the Umwelt mentioned
above. This is in contradistinction to objects or artefacts, as argued by the bio-
logical phenomenologist Hans Jonas:
[…] to the artifact the identity is accorded; and, insofar as this requires a
continuity of memory and tradition in those who do accord it, the identity
is the function of another identity, namely, that established in memory, indi-
vidual and social. This originative identity of the cognitive subject is a pre-
requisite for the accorded identity of the object. But this original identity,
being that of living systems, is […] owned by, not loaned to its subject.
(Jonas, 1968, p. 239-240, cited by Barandiaran et al., 2009, p. 3)
The second is interactional asymmetry, which changes the “structural cou-
pling” provided in the original definition of enaction (see above). On the basis of
this:
[…] an agent is a source of activity, not merely a passive sufferer of the effects
of external forces. Similarly, an agent is not driven to act by internal, sub-
systemic modules, which subordinates the system to the triggering or isolated
functioning of a local mechanism. In a sense yet to be properly disclosed, an
agent as a whole drives itself, breaking the symmetry of its coupling with the
environment so as to modulate it from within. (Barandiaran et al., 2009, p. 4)
Still, there are cases that fulfil these two conditions, but are not truly agentive, for
example the tremors of a Parkinson patient. What the person who performs invol-
untary movements in this manner lacks for this to be a case of agency is the condi-
tion of normativity, implying that agents actively regulate their interactions with the
environment on the basis of “goals or norms according to which they are acting, pro-
viding a sort of reference condition” (ibid. p.5). Further, this is intrinsically linked
to the individuality condition: “component reactions must occur in a certain manner
in order for the very system to keep going, environmental conditions are good or
bad for the continuation of the system, the system can fail to regain stability after
a perturbation, etc.” (ibid. p. 7). Thus, this (broad) notion of normativity is more or
less equivalent to that of intrinsic value (Zlatev, 2003): the agent is not “optimizing”
some function attributed from outside, but acting on the basis of their own, possibly
internalized, values.
151A Cognitive-Semiotic Approach to Agency: Assessing Ideas…Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 12

1 3Combined, the conditions are formulated into a “generative definition”, the short
version of which holds that: “an agent is an autonomous organization capable of
adaptively regulating its coupling with the environment according to the norms
established by its own viability conditions (ibid. p. 8) and illustrated in a figure,
which we reproduce in Fig. 3.
An advantage of this approach and definition of agency is that it is general, and
can apply to bacteria “performing metabolic-dependent chemotaxis” (ibid. p.7),
but also to “other domains” (ibid. p. 8), and is not strictly limited to individual liv-
ing organisms. Thus, it is not susceptible to accusations of “vitalism”. On the other
hand, it maintains a clear distinction between agency and causality, and between
agents and artefacts, unlike the approach that we discuss in the following sub-sec-
tion. By understanding agency as a form of “being-in-the-world”, it has at least
family-resemblance with our own approach (compare Figs. 2 and 3). It is neverthe-
less too general from the perspective of our approach, which to remind, requires any
degree of agency to be in principle matched with a corresponding degree of subjec-
tivity, a sense of agency. Since this is explicitly what Barandiaran et al. (2009) wish
to avoid, their “minimal definition” grants agency to bacteria, and possibly even arti-
ficial systems, as long as these fulfil the conditions mentioned. But as pointed out by
(Thompson, 2007, p. 162), even if supplemented with “sense-making”:
There is no good reason, however, for thinking that autopoietic selfhood […]
involves any kind of intentional access on the part of the organism to its self-
making. Second, it seems unlikely that minimal autopoietic selfhood involves
phenomenal selfhood or subjectivity, in the sense of pre-reflective self-aware-
ness constitutive of a phenomenal first-person perspective.
Thus, while we do not wish to deny the value of the authors’ “minimal defini-
tion” for some domains of study like artificial life, we must conclude that it is too
minimal to meet our intuitions of agency, which require a first-person experience, or
Fig. 3 An illustration of the enactive definition of agency; the system is constituted by a self-sustained
network of processes coupled asymmetrically and normatively with the environment. Taken from Baran-
diaran et al., 2009, Fig. 1
152 J. Mendoza-Collazos, J. ZlatevContent courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 13

1 3sense, of agency, even in the most minimal manner. Without this, there is no way to
perform pheno-methodological triangulation (see Section 2), given that there is no
first-person or second-person perspective according to which subjectivity or sense of
agency can be attributed to the simplest living organisms, and even less so to their
constituents such as organs or cells.
Hence, we would need to supplement this approach with first-person experience,
and thus phenomenology, moving from sense-making to meaning making (Zlatev,
2018). Barandiaran et al. (2009) are well aware that their approach would require
further developments, given that it is focused very much on the “minimal” crite-
ria. For example, it does not deal at all with what we called enhanced agency: with
tools, signs and language (see Table 1). Toward the end of their paper, they mark
this as terrain for future work:
How does niche construction (for example) relate to agency? Should those
environmental features that recurrently depend on the agent be considered as
part of the agent? What is the status of tools as mediators between agents and
environments? (ibid. p.11)
As we show below, some have asked such questions, but reached very different
conclusions from those of the enactive approach of Barandiaran et al. (2009).
An Extended Approach to Agency
The move to “extend” the mind beyond not only the brain, but also the body and
its “naked” interactions with the world is currently a popular one (Menary, 2010).
Despite criticising many tenets of the general extended mind approach, above all
on claims of not being radical enough, the Material Engagement Theory developed
by Malafouris and colleagues, e.g. (Malafouris, 2013) can be taken as representa-
tive. Battling internalism, especially in its cognitivist mind-as-computer variety,
and anthropocentrism, the theory endorses the notion of material agency, meant
to serve as “a wake-up call, for social scientists and archaeologists, to encourage
them to consider agency non-anthropocentrically, as a situated process in which
material culture is entangled” (Knappett & Malafouris, 2008, p. xii). While Mala-
fouris (2013) adopts a bold form of “methodological fetishism”: “it is more sensible
and productive to treat material things as agents (and be wrong) than to deny their
agency (and be wrong)” (ibid.: 134), the claim seems to be not that artefacts quite
literally have an agency of their own, but rather that agency is a by-product, and
emergent property of material engagement.
The theory is also sceptical of other internalist notions like mental imagery and
prior intentions, accepting at most intentions-in-action (Searle, 1983)—illustrated in
Section 2 with the spontaneous act of running to catch a departing bus—modulated
by the material agency of their situatedness. As for sign processes, the approach
attempts to define a notion of enactive signs, emerging not as representations of what
they denote, but through sensori-motor engagements with materials and surfaces,
153A Cognitive-Semiotic Approach to Agency: Assessing Ideas…Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 14

1 3thus producing, for example, drawings that can only post-hoc be seen as depictions
of, for instance, animals on a cave wall.
Comparing this with our cognitive-semiotic approach, but also with the enactive
approach of Barandiaran et al. (2009), there is very little in common, apart from
the ideological rejection of cognitivism. To begin with, there is nothing correspond-
ing to the “originative identity of the cognitive subject” in sense of Hans Jonas (see
above), or the original agency of our model. Intentions-in-action are recognized, but
apparently only in combination with artefacts. Therefore, it is not clear how Mala-
fouris would treat the agency of the runner, the high-jumper or the dance group (see
Section 2, Table 1). In addition, while this is probably not his intention, the theory
implies hardly any agency to non-human animals, given that their interaction with
objects (and even more making of artefacts) is minimal.
Turning to enhanced agency, there are clearly cases where intentions-in-action
may predominate, for instance, in trained and sedimented bodily movements
required to operate a tool, as the joystick of videogames. But what lends human
actions, with or without objects, distinctive creativity is arguably reflective agency,
as in sculpting a statue, and joint agency, as in constructing a maloca, an Amazonian
community house (Mendoza-Collazos & Sonesson, 2021). In fact, there is on-going
interaction between prior intentions and intention-in-action in all human, and even
some non-human, activities, as can be witnessed in the activities of the chimpanzee
Santino who famously collected and hid stones in caches, so that he could throw
them at irritating humans when the zoo opened on a later occasion (Osvath, 2009).
In sum, the theory of Malafouris and colleagues, and more generally the
“extended mind” approach, might help fill a gap by focusing on enhanced rather
than original agency (in our terms), and may serve as an antidote to excessive reli-
ance on “internal” takes on representations and intentionality (in both the philosoph-
ical and psychological senses of the term). However, the theory denies, or at least
omits, essential properties of agency. One is the fundamentally asymmetrical rela-
tionship between the subject/agent and the environment, and even the basic individ-
uality (identity) of the agent, both (correctly) emphasised as definitional of agency
(Barandiaran et al., 2009). Consequently, there is not even the possibility of accom-
modating our definitional condition: subjectivity, or first-person phenomenal experi-
ence (Section 2). Thus, the theory denies a central consequence of our approach:
that the agency of artefacts is derived (Mendoza-Collazos, 2016; Niño, 2015); simi-
lar to non-verbal signs and languages, they need to be used, interpreted, or adapted
by human beings in human cultures. Thus, the differences between cognitive-semi-
otic and material engagement approaches to agency far outweigh any similarities
(Mendoza-Collazos, 2020).
A Cognitive‑Phenomenological Approach to Agency
Following up on the inspirations from phenomenology in the early work on
enaction (Varela et al., 1991), but elaborating phenomenological concepts and
methods considerably, researchers like Thompson (2007) and Gallagher (2005)
have over the past decades helped establish a hybrid field at the intersection of
154 J. Mendoza-Collazos, J. ZlatevContent courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 15

1 3phenomenology and cognitive science (Gallagher & Schmicking, 2010; Gallagher
& Zahavi, 2012). It is this that we refer to as “cognitive phenomenology”, and the
topic of agency is often discussed within it, commonly discussed employing the
term “sense of agency”. But as Gallagher (2012, inter alia) points out, this is a
complex notion with many layers.
Initially, Gallagher (2000) distinguished two phenomenological dimensions in
relation to movement, both “closely related aspects of minimal self-awareness:
self-ownership – the sense that it is my body that is moving; and self-agency – the
sense that I am the initiator or source of the action”. (Gallagher, 2000, p. 16).
Often, only the latter is referred to as “sense of agency” (SoA), and opposed to
“sense of ownership” (SoO), but baring pathological conditions like schizophre-
nia, or anarchic hand syndrome, and unless it is someone or something else that
has propelled my movement (see Section 2), the kinaesthetic sense of my body
in motion implies at least a minimal sense of agency, understood as “a matter of
very thin, pre-reflective awareness” (Gallagher & Zahavi, 2012, p. 177). In addi-
tion to kinaesthesia, discussed at length by Sheets-Johnstone (2011), there are
two aspects to such pre-reflective sense/experience of agency. The first has to do
with the urge to move, linked with motor control, and the second with monitoring
the effect that one’s movement has produced (Gallagher, 2012). All these pre-
reflective experiential aspects of agency correspond to the operative agency layer
of our model.
But as Gallagher and colleagues (sometimes, but not always) admit, there is
more to (the sense of) agency than this, focusing on the goal, and reflecting on
the means that would be most appropriate to achieve it. Obviously, this amount to
a layer of reflective agency:
For other actions, however, the sense of agency is not reducible to just these
embodied and pre-reflective processes. In addition, in many cases we may
be reflectively conscious of and concerned about what we are doing. For
such actions our sense of agency […] will be tied to a more reflective sense
of intention, by which our attention is directed toward the project or task
that we are engaged in, or toward the means and/or end that we aim for.
(Gallagher, 2012)
Such reflections do not require language, or any other form of sign use, and hence
cannot be a matter of narrative-based attributions of agency, of the kind that are
assumed to arise as post-hoc rationalisations of our actions by some researchers,
inspired by philosophers like Dennett (1991), who claim that self-agency, or even
more free will, is a convenient fiction:
[T]he subject’s sense of agency regarding her thoughts likewise depends on
her belief that these mental episodes are expressions of her intentional states.
That is, whether the subject regards an episode of thinking occurring in her
psychological history as something she does, as her mental action, depends on
whether she finds its occurrence explicable in terms of her theory or story of
her own underlying intentional states (Graham & Stephens, 1994, p. 102, cited
by Gallagher, 2012)
155A Cognitive-Semiotic Approach to Agency: Assessing Ideas…Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 16

1 3As Gallagher and colleagues point out, this could indeed be the case sometimes,
for example when participants in experiments use “folk psychological narratives”
(Hutto, 2008) to make sense of their own actions, especially when these are manipu-
lated, as in so-called “choice-blindness” studies, more properly referred to as (par-
tial) manipulation blindness (Mouratidou, 2019). But these are very special cases,
and they can hardly apply to the basic layers of operative agency (in our terms), or
even to non-verbal reflections, such as evinced in non-human animals, as the stone
caching and throwing chimpanzee Santino (see Section 2).
It is easy to notice the consilience between this approach to agency and our own,
given the roots of both in phenomenology. As Gallagher and Zahavi (2012, p.177)
stress, “we understand agency, in its proper sense, to depend on the agent’s con-
sciousness of agency”, even if this consciousness is, as pointed out, marginal or
recessive. Further, agency (and its experience) is readily admitted to be complex,
with dimensions that correspond to layers in our model. Given our summary above,
there are at least five different aspects (kinaesthesia, urge, expected effect, reflection
and narrative), and three different layers (operative, reflective, language-mediated)
of the sense of agency, when conceiving this broadly. And at the same time, we
agree that many of these layers are not easily distinguished, since they intertwine
and form a composite experience:
Although conceptually we may distinguish between different levels (first-
order, higher-order), and neuroscientifically we may be able to identify dif-
ferent brain processes responsible for these different contributories, in our
everyday phenomenology we tend to experience agency in a more holistic,
qualitative, and ambiguous experience that might be open to a description in
terms of degrees of control. (Gallagher, 2012)
As this citation implies, the cognitive-phenomenological approach to agency has
implications for the neuroscience of agency, which we address in the following sec-
tion. But we must comment on a limitation: by focusing on the lowest layers of (the
sense of) agency, the theory has little to tell us about agency enhanced with arte-
facts, signs and language, or even about the joint agency of several people (or other
agents) pooling their actions together to form a collective agent of sorts.
Summary
The three different approaches to agency in cognitive science that we discussed have
complementary strengths and weaknesses, especially when seen from the perspec-
tive of our proposal of the agency hierarchy. The enactive approach of Barandiaran
and colleagues contributes with a very useful threshold between minimal agency—
on the basis of the conditions of individuality, normativity, interactional asymme-
try—and non-agency, the latter characteristic of artefacts. But given that they do
not consider the first-person experience/sense of agency as criterial as we do, this
threshold is placed somewhat too low.
The phenomenological approach of Gallagher and colleagues, with its distinc-
tions within the experience of agency, is most compatible with the layered approach
156 J. Mendoza-Collazos, J. ZlatevContent courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 17

1 3of our agency hierarchy. Similarly to our principle of pheno-methodological triangu-
lation, it opens up for operationalizations in terms of third-person methods such as
those of neuroscience, as we discuss in the following section. The main lack in this
approach was that by focusing so much on the experience (sense) of agency within
a single person, dimensions (layers) such as joint agency, and agency extended by
artefacts, signs and language are largely bypassed—with the possible exception of
language-based narratives, for (self) agency attributions.
By rather focusing on artefacts and to some extent on signs (though interpreted in
a much too anti-representational way, from our point of view), the de facto extended
approach of Malafouris and colleagues (despite their reservations towards the term
“extended mind”) can be said to help fill this gap. However, by being so concerned
to avoid Cartesian dualism in its quest for interdependent relationship between mate-
rial things and human beings, this approach misses the strengths of the others: a
clear distinction between agency and causality, with artefacts lacking the former,
and downplaying the consciousness of agents proper, acknowledging at most inten-
tions-in-action. In sum, we propose that our cognitive-semiotic approach and its
agency hierarchy is capable of accommodating the strengths of these models, while
bypassing their problems.
Assessing Approaches to Agency in Neuroscience
The Technology, its Problems and Potentials
Cognitive neuroscience has grown exponentially in the past two decades, largely due
to the invention of a diversity of advanced techniques for brain imaging like com-
puter tomography, positron emission tomography, ultrasound, and magnetic resonance
imaging (Agnihotri et al., 2010; Bradshaw, 1989). Unlike the others, however, func-
tional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) is commonly applied in studies that are
not part of clinical research and the technique most widely used in the neuroscience
of agency (David, 2012).4 Despite its relatively low temporal resolution, fMRI allows
studying both the connectivity and dynamics of brain activity while the person is
engaged in particular tasks, which explains its current popularity. This technique uses
radiation of strong magnetic fields to manipulate hydrogen molecules of the brain,
tracing the activity of neurons, based on signals generated by the blood-oxygen level:
more presence of blood-oxygen is assumed to indicate more neural activation (Jenkin-
son & Chappell, 2018). In this way, experimenters are able to register the activity of
the brain triggered by particular stimuli, comparing across conditions or with a base-
line condition, usually a resting state with spontaneous neural activity.
4 According to David (2012, p. 3): “only a few authors explicitly approached the sense of agency with
EEG (Gentsch et al., 2012; Gentsch & Schütz-Bosbach, 2011; Kühn et al., 2011), exclusively focusing
on event-related potentials. This classical approach, however, can tell us only little about temporal brain
dynamics occurring during agentic processing; rather, it represents a static snapshot of the brain’s activ-
ity at the scalp level”.
157A Cognitive-Semiotic Approach to Agency: Assessing Ideas…Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 18

1 3Although fMRI has many strong points such as high spatial resolution and non-
invasive imaging of the tissues in the brain, many researchers within the neurosci-
ence of agency point out numerous methodological and technical challenges (see
Braun et al., 2018; Crivelli & Balconi, 2017; David, 2012; Grünbaum & Chris-
tensen, 2020; Herdova, 2016; Seghezzi et al., 2019; Zito et al., 2020). For instance,
voluntary and involuntary movements of participants (due to discomfort provoked
by the scanner) give rise to low-quality data. Other sources of distortions commonly
mentioned are materials interference, air-filled sinuses or dental works, which pro-
duce inhomogeneities in the magnetic fields leading to miscalculated locations of
brain activity. Such errors are said to be “routinely dealt with by the analysis meth-
ods” (Jenkinson & Chappell, 2018, p. 21), but statistical corrections are subject of
controversy (Brown & Behrmann, 2017). According to Elliott et al. (2020), statis-
tical weakness due to small samples, as well as problems in experimental designs
have led to extensive variations, and even apparently contradictory findings across
studies.
Some of these problems could presumably be resolved by increasing statistical
power and fine-tuning methodologies; these are outside of the scope of our topic,
and indeed outside of our competence. However, there are more serious issues
with the neuroscience of agency that we believe that our approach can help address
such as: (a) category errors attempting to literally trace agency in the brain, and
(b) issues of construct validity, making it unclear what aspect of agency is being
operationalized in particular studies, leading in turn to apparently contradictory
findings. We illustrate these problems briefly in Section 4.2, while in Section 4.3,
we suggest a “reorganization” of the different experimental paradigms used in the
field based on the distinctions made in Section 3.3, before summarizing in Sec-
tion 4.4.
Reductionism and Construct Validity
An implicit and sometimes explicit assumption made by many, albeit not all, neuro-
scientists is that agency, or at least the “sense of agency” which may very well be an
illusion (Dennett, 1991), is to be found in the activity of the brain. For example, in
an extensive review of the field, Haggard (2017 p. 206) claims: “The human sense
of agency is not a transcendental feature of human nature but the result of specific
activity in the brain circuits that underlie voluntary motor control”. A similar view
is, for example, expressed by Yomogida et al. (2010, p. 198).
One of the most vocal critics of misguided neuro-reductionism in recent years has
been Raymond Tallis, referring to it as “neuromania” (Tallis, 2016). Its main fault
is confusing the “the realm of life, meaning and purpose” with that of “cause and
effect, mechanisms and physical laws” (Tallis, 2016, p. 155). Given that agency (like
subjectivity and intentionality) belongs to the first of these realms, it is what phi-
losophers refer to as a “category error” to look for either identity or (direct) causal-
ity between biochemical processes on the one hand, and consciousness and experi-
ence on the latter. Tallis is by no means adverse to research elucidating correlations,
especially when understood as distinct from causation (Aneshensel, 2012), between
158 J. Mendoza-Collazos, J. ZlatevContent courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 19

1 3neural activity and various states of consciousness. What he opposes are simplistic
views of the latter, with multiple references to “illusions of selfhood” ignoring the
first-person experiences of human beings. It is, for example, a fundamental fact of
such experience that our actions cannot be reduced to a causal chain of physical
events, given that each action is not driven by an isolated goal but rooted in a tempo-
ral depth, embedded in the sense of past and future. Thus, expressions of agency do
not respond to the rules of survival, and cannot be (fully) explained by unconscious
activity of the brain controlling the flux of dopamine. As summarized in a similar
critique by Fuchs (2017, p. 207):
[…] the mind is not in the brain for it is the overarching manifestation, the
gestalt, and the ordered patterns of all relations that we have to our environ-
ment as animate beings, and as humans to our fellow humans.
This implies that neural activity should not be understood as the cause of agency,
and localizations of greater activity of neurons in certain regions of the brain cannot
be equated with (the sense of) agency. Still, while agency cannot be found in neural
processes, given that the brain is a highly relevant functional organ of the human
body, it is valid to search for correlations between first-person experiential states,
and third-person data produced by fMRI studies, as long as we are careful in how we
interpret the latter, for example as done within neurophenomenology (Varela, 1996).
Here, however, the second major problem arises: how to define the various theo-
retical constructs of agency in a way that corresponds to the phenomenon of agency,
i.e. with a high degree of construct validity. In an extensive review, Grünbaum and
Christensen (2020) argue that such validity is generally low in the field, since it is
not clear what the constructs are, and if a set of experimental procedures is really
measuring a given construct or not. Most neuroscientists of agency operate with the
two constructs of “sense of agency” (SoA) and “sense of ownership” (SoO), assum-
ing, for example, that stronger efferent (“outgoing”) signals generating a movement
correspond to stronger SoA, and stronger afferent sensory feedback would corre-
spond to SoO. But as pointed out in Section 3.3, it is far from clear that these two
constructs correspond to clearly distinct experiences. On the other hand, there are
quite different aspects of (the sense of) agency, from the urge to move to attribu-
tions of agency that do need to be distinguished before neural correlations are to be
sought (see, e.g. Gallagher & Zahavi, 2012, p. 182). What we propose in the follow-
ing section is to distinguish some of the experimental paradigms used in the field,
and to map them to distinctions that have been made in the cognitive-phenomeno-
logical approach to agency. This would improve the validity of the various construct
of agency in the field, and avoid the problem of contradictory claims on the location
of neural correlates of agency.
Improving Construct Validity in the Neuroscience of Agency
Taking into account the five aspects of agency that have been characterized by
Gallagher and colleagues (see Section 3.3): kinaesthetic, urge, expected effects,
159A Cognitive-Semiotic Approach to Agency: Assessing Ideas…Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 20

1 3reflection, and self-attribution, we can distinguish the following experimental para-
digms in the field, each with their corresponding constructs:
Kinaesthetic and Urge Paradigms
The kinaesthetic aspect of agency is a minimal sense of agency at the pre-reflective
level of operative agency. There seems to be little investigations into what the neural
correlations of this could be, but it is sometimes said that this is “peripheral experi-
ence” relayed by the activity of somatosensory receptors (Haggard, 2017, p, 198).
A clearer sense of agency requires according to Haggard (2017) an internal state
of volition or ‘urge’ to move connected to motor control. In a typical paradigm at
this level, experimenters ask participants to perform a simple task (e.g. move a han-
dle, press a button, press a key) under two conditions. In one condition, the move-
ment is produced by the participant (so-called “active agency”); in the other condi-
tion, the movement is automatically performed by a customized device (so-called
“passive agency”). Using this approach, Uhlmann et al. (2020) observed variations
in neural processing under the two conditions. Interestingly, the researchers found a
reduction of neural activity in the condition of active agency in the areas shown in
Fig. 4a, explaining this as follows: “Agency cues consume less resources when par-
ticipants are able to predict the sensory consequences of their action, that is, when
they actively move their own hand” (Uhlmann et al., 2020, p. 2484). Further, they
found certain motor-related areas (Fig. 4b) to be active in both conditions, which
could possibly be associated with a kinaesthetic aspect of agency: the minimal sense
of agency at the most pre-reflective level.
Expected Effect Paradigms
To study the result-expectation aspect of agency, experimenters investigate the neu-
ral “processing” associated with action-outcome monitoring: how the brain responds
in connection with expected outcomes (Haggard, 2017). Participants are typically
asked to estimate the time interval between an action (e.g. pressing a button) and its
outcome (e.g. a tone), while researchers compare the neural response to delayed sen-
sory feedback with the response to non-delayed sensory feedback. For instance, van
Fig. 4 (a) Brain regions with a suppression of neural activity when participants actively move their own
hand. (b) Brain motor network active in both conditions (voluntary movement of the handle and auto-
matically moved). Brain images based on Uhlmann et al. (2020)
160 J. Mendoza-Collazos, J. ZlatevContent courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 21

1 3Kemenade et al. (2017) analysed the neural comparator processes during detections
of delays. They asked the participants to perform simple button presses, which either
produce a tone or present a dot on the screen, or both. The effects of button presses
were delayed with a variable amount of milliseconds and participants were asked to
judge if they noticed the delay. The findings indicated the importance of a key area,
the angular gyrus, which functioned as a “supramodal comparator”, given that it
was involved in the delayed detection of visual, auditory or combined feedback (van
Kemenade et al., 2017, p. 3699, see Fig. 5). Presumably, this can be generalized to
stating that the angular gyrus plays a key role in action–outcome monitoring, but
more research is needed to be able to conclude this with any certainty.
Reflection Paradigms
Even more cognitive demanding aspects of agency are involved when the agent is
focusing on a task requiring conscious attention and reflection. Participants in this
kind of experiment are asked to choose among alternatives or to perform an action
under different conditions requiring their attention. Neural activity is compared
between different choices and conditions. Gertz et al. (2016) applied this paradigm
to examine the neural correlates in perception–action couplings and the role of
beliefs about the origins of a particular movement. The subjects were asked to track
a moving dot on the screen to measure brain activation during oculomotor tracking
and were told that the dot could be moved either by a human agent or by a computer
program.
By manipulating instructions about the movement (originator and velocity) dur-
ing this oculomotor tracking task, experimenters searched for the neural correlates
of participants beliefs about the presence of human agency on dynamic percep-
tion–action coupling: a very different construct compared to those investigated in
the studies reviewed so far. The condition where they were told that the dot was
moved by a person revealed higher activation in areas such as the frontal pole, the
superior frontal gyrus, the anterior cingulate cortex, the posterior cingulate cortex,
and in the frontal medial cortex (Gertz et al., 2016, p. 116, see Fig. 6).
Fig. 5 Angular gyrus is associ-
ated with the detection of
delayed feedback during action–
outcome monitoring. Brain
images based on van Kemenade
et al. (2017)
161A Cognitive-Semiotic Approach to Agency: Assessing Ideas…Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 22

1 3Attribution-Based Paradigms
Attributions of agency, rather that perceptions or even judgments of agency are
more distanced from direct experience, and could in principle be due to an “illu-
sion”, where agency is attributed on the basis of a mistaken belief. In experimen-
tal paradigms that seem to target this aspect of agency, participants are sometimes
asked to report who is the author of a specific bodily movement, under conditions
of ambiguity. For instance, de Bézenac et al. (2016) investigated events in which the
cause of an action is not clear or shared between various agents. Participants were
asked to perform taps on a keyboard and listen to tones, which could result either
from their own hand’s movements or from that of another agent (de Bézenac et al.,
2016, p. 67). Participants reported the level of control that they felt, that is, if they
thought that the tone was produced by their tapings or by the tapings of others. The
finding showed variations of neural processing in subcortical regions such as the
accumbens, caudate, putamen, thalamus, and the cerebellum (see Fig. 7), under the
different conditions of agency attribution, e.g. self vs. other.
Summary
Recent neuroscience research on agency seems to be thriving, based on the large
number of publications. Yet, as we indicated above, there are still basic technical as
well as theoretical problems to be resolved. Admittedly, most researchers are not as
naïve as to conflate neural activity (even more, oxygen level variations) with agency
and its sense in a one-to-one manner. However, even when investigating “correla-
tions” and “associations”, it is not always clear what theoretical constructs of agency
are being used. By distinguishing different aspects of agency with the help of the
cognitive-phenomenological approach (Section 3.3) we were able to map these to
distinct experimental studies in way that makes it clear that their findings of very
different brain areas as neural correlates of agency are not contradictory, since they
concern different constructs, and ultimately different phenomena.
Notably, as the level of agentive complexity increases, experimenters seem to
include self-reports by the participants concerning their experiences of agency,
Fig. 6 Areas of the brain with significant neural activations in dynamic perception–action coupling.
Brain images based on Gertz et al. (2016)
162 J. Mendoza-Collazos, J. ZlatevContent courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 23

1 3which goes at least somewhat in the direction of neurophenomenology. Neverthe-
less, these “subjective” aspects are generally minimized, and the artificial condi-
tions of the experiments (i.e. over-designed manipulations) are very distinct from
everyday life, leading to low ecological validity. Confusing various levels of agency,
while over distinguishing the senses of “agency vs. ownership” has made matters
even worse. Given that higher levels of agency, related to intersubjectivity and sig-
nitive intentions are hardly even explored (Tallis, 2016), we can sum up the cur-
rent situation in the field by stating an inverse proportion between the complexity of
agentive phenomena and the reliability of findings concerning correlations between
brain regions with such phenomena (correlational reliability), as shown in Fig. 8.
We would suggest that our cognitive-semiotic approach to agency could help
improve this situation. One obvious thing is to distinguish clearly between differ-
ent aspects/concepts of agency, and to map these to theoretical constructs and their
operationalizations more clearly. Another is for experimenters to use pheno-meth-
odological triangulation more explicitly, and investigate both their own, and their
participants’ experiences of agency in detail, both before and during the studies. For
example, how is the “urge” to move like, or the experiences of either confirmed or
disappointed action-outcome relation? How are attributions of self-agency similar
and different from those of others?
While emerging technologies such as hyperscanning (Misaki et al., 2021; Sadato,
2017) may allow experimenters to study the layer of joint agency, applications of
pheno-methodological triangulation would be needed to link these to real life expe-
riences. We propose that neuroscientists can benefit from our approach, and cogni-
tive semiotics more general, to study the complex layers of enhanced agency, asking
questions such as: how neural activities differ in cases of intentions-in-action and
prior intentions? How engaging with artefacts individually and collectively differ?
How thinking with the help of different sign systems correlates with differences in
Fig. 7 Neural activations in areas of the subcortical region of the brain and the cerebellum under differ-
ent conditions of agency attribution. Based on de Bézenac et al. (2016)
163A Cognitive-Semiotic Approach to Agency: Assessing Ideas…Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 24

1 3agency? Being able to address such questions adequately would more certainly help
“straighten up” the red correlational line in Fig. 8, that is, increasing the reliability
of studies seeking to establish neural correlates of specific levels of agency.
Summary and Conclusions
We started by pointing out that agency has been understood in either extremely
broad or extremely narrow terms, causing confusion with respect to this central phil-
osophical and semiotic concept. With its aim of providing a sort of “middle ground”
between ontological and epistemological extremes, the new discipline of cognitive
semiotics (e.g. Zlatev, 2015) can hopefully help resolve this tension. Compatible
with the work of Godfrey-Smith (2020) investigating the biological and evolutionary
origins of consciousness, we proposed that agency should be seen as the active, self-
generated aspect of intentionality, coupled with subjectivity, the receptive aspect of
intentionality, or its “qualitative feel”. This implies that any form of agency must
correlate with at least some degree of consciousness: a sense/feeling of agency.
This excludes artefacts, inert matter, causality and simpler forms of life as proper
agents, reserving agency for animals with unitary bodies and integrated sensory-
motor systems. Combining this with the layered understanding of intentionality as
in the Semiotic Hierarchy (Zlatev, 2018), and the distinction between original and
enhanced agency (Mendoza-Collazos & Sonesson, 2021), we were led to a model of
an agency hierarchy consisting of six layers, only some of which imply the capacity
for reflective consciousness, and deliberate choice making.
Human beings, while sharing the layers of operative and even reflective agency
with other creatures add to these higher levels of agency, and especially those in
enhanced agency, which define human uniqueness: technology, sign-use and lan-
guage-mediated agency. Importantly, such a model does not imply a return to the
Fig. 8 Reliability of experimental paradigms and the complexity of agentive phenomena: an inverse cor-
relation
164 J. Mendoza-Collazos, J. ZlatevContent courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.

Page 25

1 3hierarchical anthropocentrism of a scala naturae, since the relations between lay-
ers is dialectical and based on the phenomenological notion of Fundierung. Still,
defending a particular notion of human uniqueness is necessary despite current fears
of “exceptionalism”. As Tallis (2016) warns, denying human uniqueness amounts
to diluting human agency not only in its philosophical but also in its political sense:
eroding the possibility of channelling our destiny into a better world.
Our cognitive-semiotic proposal of an agency hierarchy follows the principles
of cognitive semiotics, given that it was (a) defined on the basis of a conceptual-
empirical loop and (b) based on first-person (intuition-based) analysis, second per-
son (empathy, intersubjective corroboration) and, at least potentially, third-person
(empirical) methods, including those of cognitive science and neuroscience. This
led us to engage more explicitly with approaches to agency in these two fields.
Concerning cognitive science, in Section 3 our model was shown for the most
part to be in conflict with extended approaches that attribute agency to artefacts,
but much more consistent with enactive approaches, where agency is clearly dis-
tinguished from causality, and based on features such as individuality and intrinsic
normativity. Still, given that subjectivity is not included in this list, we found even
the enactive approach too inclusive. It is rather the cognitive-phenomenological
approach, with its fine attention to different aspects of agency that we found our-
selves in most of agreement with.
Turning the approaches to agency from neuroscience in Section 4, we found that
some researchers are still subject to naïve views of identity (or causality) between neu-
ral and experiential processes, including those of agency. Even those who speak more
carefully of correlations are seldom clear about what aspect (or level) of agency is
being operationalized, leading to low construct (as well as ecological) validity. Using
phenomenological distinctions of agency, we showed examples of at least four different
experimental paradigms with target different aspects of agency, making it less mysteri-
ous that they find correlations with very different neural processes and brain areas.
It is possible that emerging techniques could potentially avoid some of these
problems, as long as they are framed on a refined theoretical approach such as our
cognitive-semiotic model of agency. This can expand the scope of neuroscience
beyond simple bodily movements in artificial conditions. Our conjecture is that if
cognitive (neuro)scientists would adopt a version of our pheno-methodological tri-
angulation more explicitly, they would be able to start with the actual experiences
of agency, both their own and those of their participants, and design studies that are
more theoretically and ecologically valid. This, on its part, would improve the corre-
lation between reliability and the complexity of agentive phenomena, which is cur-
rently far from optimal. Finally, this would allow the cognitive semiotics of agency
to engage more fully with third-person methods, and thus to conclude the iteration
of the conceptual-empirical loop depicted in Fig